Blog

Defining Virtue

July 22, 2016

Thanks to Alissa Simon, HMU Tutor, for today's post.

In “Meno”, Socrates and Meno attempt to define virtue. Here is Meno's first attempt: “Let us take the first virtue of a man – he should know how to administer the state, and in the administration of it to benefit his friends and harm his enemies and he must also be careful not to suffer harm himself. A woman's virtue, if you wish to know about that, may also be easily described: her duty is to order her house, and keep what is indoors, and obey her husband. Every age, every condition of life, young or old, male or female, bond or free, has a different virtue: there are virtues numberless, and no lack of definitions for them; for virtue is relative to the actions and ages of each of us in all that we do.” In the end, this dialogue never does define virtue specifically, but discusses the way that it acts within society. They do decide that there is an element of knowledge or education in virtue. However, they decide that virtue cannot be delivered solely by education due to the fact that virtuous parents do not have virtuous children.

“Protagoras” also discusses the idea of virtue in another attempt to define it. In this dialogue, Protagoras and Socrates decide that virtue is composed of justice, temperance and holiness, and also includes wisdom and courage. They continue to list these as parts of virtue. Therefore, the reader is still left without an understanding of virtue as one complete entity. Socrates makes an argument that virtue is habitual, but Protagoras believes it is more likely a teachable knowledge. In the end, Protagoras and Socrates end up on opposite sides of the question from where they started. Protagoras unwillingly admits that there is an indemonstrable element of virtue, whereas Socrates wants to prove that it is teachable. They do agree, however, that virtue is necessary for a good life, and that is where the conversation ends.

Aristotle, also, struggles to define virtue. Aristotle places wisdom, prudence, art, science and “intuitive reason” under virtue's umbrella. However, he asserts that virtues such as art and science do not solely belong, but can exist apart from virtue. He claims that virtues depend upon common prudence. It is difficult to define, however, what common prudence. Also difficult to answer is who or what generates it. Is prudence granted by God? Is it driven by custom and society? Or is it an internal register? For Aristotle, virtue is a mean between two vices. For example, a miser sits on one side of the line with greed at the opposite end and virtue in between.

Francis Bacon may agree with the idea of virtue being on a continuum. Bacon indicates that both nature and education play a part in the understanding of virtue as it may lead to vice. He writes, “[T]he minds of all men are at some times in a state more perfect, and at other times in a state more depraved.” However, Bacon believes that through education, man may lift himself (or keep himself constantly pointed towards) virtuous behavior. He alludes to this same principle when he writes of Psalm 61 which shows that measure is better than excess. The Psalm reads: “If riches fly to thee, set not they heart upon them”. Bacon interprets the riches as a luxury, but not a necessity. For him, it is important to know what one requires, versus what excesses can be enjoyed responsibly.

There is an interesting dialogue between Aristotle and Bacon regarding the metaphysical aspect of virtue. Whether or not virtue comes from God is unknowable, but both Bacon and Aristotle separate out human versus deity. In Advancement of Learning, Bacon notes that charity fastens together all virtue – he calls it the “bond of perfection”. He separates the body from the mind in the same manner that he separates God's goodness and love from man's.

Hegel, too, investigates this idea of virtue as it plays out on the stage of world history. His universal view is unique and offers insight into the way that virtue may grow or change with time and civilization. For example, he notes a few great men who exemplify virtue when they stand apart from their time. They were larger than their immediate reality. In the “Philosophy of History”, he writes of Socrates that, “Though Socrates himself continued to perform his duties as a citizen, it was not the actual state and its religion, but the world of thought that was his true home.” In other words, Socrates outgrew the physicality of the state, and Hegel labels this as part of his virtue. He calls these larger-than-life individuals “world-historical individuals” and in them Hegel identifies the principle of his universal spirit.

Ironically, Hegel's logic behind the universal spirit depends upon the build-up of individual virtue at the same time that it ignores individual virtues. He believes that individuals know what is right and good, and someone without this moral register has an idle mind and a feeble will. State laws direct should suffice for an understanding of virtue in context of a particular society's rules. This character does not interest Hegel. Instead, he looks to those who acted against or beyond accepted moral standards as a historical figure who identifies a rupture of universal (“essential”) virtue with the local, societally structured version of virtue. For example, he describes Caesar's actions as “an unconscious impulse that occasioned the accomplishment of that for which the time was ripe”. For Hegel, then, individuals maintain any number of virtues, but universal virtue is singular, one entity united in a complex, but seemingly random pattern composed of the accumulation of virtuous individuals across time and civilization.

Virtue is an endlessly interesting topic. For more information on virtue, check out the References and Cross-References sections listed under the idea of "Virtue and Vice" in the Syntopicon. It is one of the most popular ideas and intersects with many other great ideas. Also, continue to check in with the blog in the next couple of months as we will continue to develop an understanding of virtue.

To post a comment, click on the title of this blog and scroll down.

Poetry

February 26, 2016

Thanks to Alissa Simon, HMU Tutor, for today's post.

Defining poetry is next to impossible, and I have been studying it for as long as I can remember. Its power thrills me. The fact that poetry escapes definition really seems appropriate to me. In an effort to wrangle with some of the ideas of poetry, I have composed a sort of poem out of fragments of my own words in combination with other authors who I greatly admire. It was meant as an exercise towards understanding, but grows immeasurably as the words are read and shared and re-read. Feel free to share your thoughts on poetry as well. And as always - enjoy!


Poetry

1] A point is that which has no part/ 2] And a line is length without breadth/ 3] And the extremities of a line are points.(1)

Perihelion. Compare aphelion.

The still point of a turning world.(2)

Ethics. Land ethics. Something about voice above silence. But also about the location of silence.

An aesthetic of embodiment.(3)

How can I be? How can I be like? How can I be in? How can we be...one?

And the shadow became Fortino and I was/ the shadow following his shadow following/ my shadow become Fortino.(4)

The overflowing of a space, meaning there is a space and it does not contain enough. The frame contains a singularity. A shadow that dances only in a memory, which grays even as it writes.

The swift, thin-waisted fish.(5)

The moment, the singularity, resurges again and again. Each generation wears it differently. Sometimes the shortest path to the point is no path at all.

Hard on the land wears the strong sea...(6)

Chopin keys a nocturne above the calming sea. Sandy beach with slanting light. Twenty six words for sol/sun/luz/light...more if you include musical expressions. And I do.

A delight, half-graspable.(7)

A red dress dances through a doorway. The doorway trimmed in light of moon; roses white and red and bleeding.

Resembling sire and child and happy mother,/ Who, all in one, one pleasing note do sing:/ Whose speechless song, being many, seeming one,/ Sings this to thee: “Thou single will prove none.”(8)

A human record. Recorded emotion acts like twine, tying events and individuals in history directly to me.

Oh! Blessed rage for order, pale Ramon,/ The maker’s rage to order words of the sea,/ Words of the fragrant portals, dimly-starred,/ And of ourselves and of our origins,/ In ghostlier demarcations, keener sounds.(9)

We think it rapid, but in fact, the evolution of truth within ourselves is exceedingly slow.

(We are all, of course, the hosts of images.)(10)

Idea/ Breath/ Sound/ Struggle/ Survival/ Song.

 

(1) Euclid's Elements, definition numbers 1-3.

(2) "Burnt Norton", T.S. Eliot.

(3) “As You Crave Soul”, Frank Bidart.

(4) Fortino Sámano (The Overflowing of the Poem), Virginie Lalucq, Jean Luc Nancy, Translated by Sylvain Gallais and Cynthia Hogue.

(5) “At Black River”, Mary Oliver.

(6) John Berryman, song 1 from 77 Dream Songs.

(7)“Endymion”, John Keats.

(8) Sonnet VIII, William Shakespeare.

(9) “The Idea of Order at Key West”, Wallace Stevens.

(10) The Way Things Are, Book III, Lucretius.

 

To post a comment, click on the title of this blog and scroll down.